Jump to content

Dense order

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Dense linear order)

In mathematics, a partial order or total order < on a set is said to be dense if, for all and in for which , there is a in such that . That is, for any two elements, one less than the other, there is another element between them. For total orders this can be simplified to "for any two distinct elements, there is another element between them", since all elements of a total order are comparable.

Example

[edit]

The rational numbers as a linearly ordered set are a densely ordered set in this sense, as are the algebraic numbers, the real numbers, the dyadic rationals and the decimal fractions. In fact, every Archimedean ordered ring extension of the integers is a densely ordered set.

Proof

For the element , due to the Archimedean property, if , there exists a largest integer with , and if , , and there exists a largest integer with . As a result, . For any two elements with , and . Therefore is dense.

On the other hand, the linear ordering on the integers is not dense.

Uniqueness for total dense orders without endpoints

[edit]

Georg Cantor proved that every two non-empty dense totally ordered countable sets without lower or upper bounds are order-isomorphic.[1] This makes the theory of dense linear orders without bounds an example of an ω-categorical theory where ω is the smallest limit ordinal. For example, there exists an order-isomorphism between the rational numbers and other densely ordered countable sets including the dyadic rationals and the algebraic numbers. The proofs of these results use the back-and-forth method.[2]

Minkowski's question mark function can be used to determine the order isomorphisms between the quadratic algebraic numbers and the rational numbers, and between the rationals and the dyadic rationals.

Generalizations

[edit]

Any binary relation R is said to be dense if, for all R-related x and y, there is a z such that x and z and also z and y are R-related. Formally:

Alternatively, in terms of composition of R with itself, the dense condition may be expressed as R ⊆ (R ; R).[3]

Sufficient conditions for a binary relation R on a set X to be dense are:

None of them are necessary. For instance, there is a relation R that is not reflexive but dense. A non-empty and dense relation cannot be antitransitive.

A strict partial order < is a dense order if and only if < is a dense relation. A dense relation that is also transitive is said to be idempotent.

See also

[edit]
  • Dense set — a subset of a topological space whose closure is the whole space
  • Dense-in-itself — a subset of a topological space such that does not contain an isolated point
  • Kripke semantics — a dense accessibility relation corresponds to the axiom

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Roitman, Judith (1990), "Theorem 27, p. 123", Introduction to Modern Set Theory, Pure and Applied Mathematics, vol. 8, John Wiley & Sons, ISBN 9780471635192.
  2. ^ Dasgupta, Abhijit (2013), Set Theory: With an Introduction to Real Point Sets, Springer-Verlag, p. 161, ISBN 9781461488545.
  3. ^ Gunter Schmidt (2011) Relational Mathematics, page 212, Cambridge University Press ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7

Further reading

[edit]